×

Just do it? When to do what you judge you ought to do. (English) Zbl 1474.03014

Summary: While it is generally believed that justification is a fallible guide to the truth, there might be interesting exceptions to this general rule. In recent work on bridge-principles, an increasing number of authors have argued that truths about what a subject ought to do are truths we stand in some privileged epistemic relation to and that our justified normative beliefs are beliefs that will not lead us astray. If these bridge-principles hold, it suggests that justification might play an interesting role in our normative theories. In turn, this might help us understand the value of justification, a value that’s notoriously difficult to understand if we think of justification as but a fallible means to a desired end. We will argue that these bridge-principles will be incredibly difficult to defend. While we do not think that normative facts necessarily stand in any interesting relationship to our justified beliefs about them, there might well be a way of defending the idea that our justified beliefs about what to do won’t lead us astray. In turn, this might help us understand the value of justification, but this way of thinking about justification and its value comes with costs few would be willing to pay.

MSC:

03A05 Philosophical and critical aspects of logic and foundations
03B42 Logics of knowledge and belief (including belief change)

References:

[1] Adler, J. (2002). Belief’s own ethics. Cambridge, MA: MIT University Press.
[2] Bird, A. (2007). Justified judging. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 81-100. · doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2007.00004.x
[3] Easwaran, K.; Branden, F.; Gendler, T. (ed.); Hawthorne, J. (ed.), Accuracy, coherence, and evidence (2014), Oxford
[4] Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an uncertain world. Oxford: Oxford University Press. · doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199550623.001.0001
[5] Gerken, M. (2011). Warrant and action. Synthese, 178, 529-547. · doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9655-0
[6] Gibbons, J. (2013). The norm of belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press. · doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199673391.001.0001
[7] Greco, D. (2014). A puzzle about epistemic Akrasia. Philosophical Studies, 167, 201-219. · doi:10.1007/s11098-012-0085-3
[8] Harman, E. (2011). Does moral ignorance exculpate. Ratio, 24, 443-468. · doi:10.1111/j.1467-9329.2011.00511.x
[9] Huemer, M.; Nuccetelli, S. (ed.); Seay, G. (ed.), Themes from G.E. Moore (2007), Oxford
[10] Kiesewetter, B. (2016). You ought to \[\phi\] ϕ only if you may believe that you ought to \[\phi\] ϕ. Philosophical Quarterly, 66, 760-782.
[11] Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (manuscript). Enkrasia or evidentialism? Learning to love mismatch.
[12] Littlejohn, C. (2012). Justification and the truth-connection. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. · doi:10.1017/CBO9781139060097
[13] Littlejohn, C.; Littlejohn, C. (ed.); Turri, J. (ed.), The unity of reason (2013), Oxford
[14] Littlejohn, C. (forthcoming). Stop Making Sense: On a Puzzle about Rationality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.
[15] McGlynn, A. (2013). Believing things unknown. Nous, 47, 385-407. · Zbl 1278.03022 · doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2011.00843.x
[16] McKinnon, R. (2015). The norms of assertion: Truth, lies, and warrant. New York: Palgrave. · doi:10.1057/9781137521729
[17] Moeller, E. (2015). Defeasible Knowledge. Oxford University DPhil Thesis.
[18] Nelkin, D. (2000). The lottery paradox, knowledge, and rationality. Philosophical Review, 109, 373-409. · doi:10.1215/00318108-109-3-373
[19] Neta, R. (2009). Treating something as a reason for action. Nous, 43, 684-699. · doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2009.00724.x
[20] Ryan, S. (1991). The preface paradox. Philosophical Studies, 64, 293-307. · doi:10.1007/BF00365003
[21] Smith, M. (2016). Between probability and certainty: What justifies belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press. · Zbl 1374.03003 · doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198755333.001.0001
[22] Smithies, D. (2012). Moore’s paradox and the accessibility of justification. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85, 273-300. · doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2011.00506.x
[23] Sorensen, R. (1995). Unknowable obligations. Utilitas, 7, 247-271. · doi:10.1017/S0953820800002077
[24] Srinivasan, A. (2015). Normativity without cartesian privilege. Philosophical Issues, 25, 273-299. · doi:10.1111/phis.12059
[25] Srinivasan, A. (2015b). Are we luminous? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90, 294-319. · doi:10.1111/phpr.12067
[26] Sutton, J. (2007). Without justification. Cambridge, MA: MIT University Press.
[27] Titelbaum, M.; Gendler, T. (ed.); Hawthorne, J. (ed.), Rationality’s fixed-point (or: In defense of right reason), No. 5 (2015), Oxford
[28] Way, J., & Whiting, D. (2016). If you justifiably believe that you ought to \[\phi\] ϕ, you ought to \[\phi\] ϕ. Philosophical Studies, 173, 1873-1895.
[29] Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[30] Williamson, T. (forthcoming). Justifications, excuses, and sceptical scenarios. In. J. Dutant & F. Dorsch (Ed.), The new evil demon problem. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[31] Worsnip, A. (2016). Belief, credence, and the preface paradox. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94, 549-562.
[32] Zimmerman, M. (2010). Living with uncertainty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. · Zbl 1233.62139
This reference list is based on information provided by the publisher or from digital mathematics libraries. Its items are heuristically matched to zbMATH identifiers and may contain data conversion errors. In some cases that data have been complemented/enhanced by data from zbMATH Open. This attempts to reflect the references listed in the original paper as accurately as possible without claiming completeness or a perfect matching.