×

Simple hyperintensional belief revision. (English) Zbl 1474.03069

Summary: I present a possible worlds semantics for a hyperintensional belief revision operator, which reduces the logical idealization of cognitive agents affecting similar operators in doxastic and epistemic logics, as well as in standard AGM belief revision theory. (Revised) belief states are not closed under classical logical consequence; revising by inconsistent information does not perforce lead to trivialization; and revision can be subject to ‘framing effects’: logically or necessarily equivalent contents can lead to different revisions. Such results are obtained without resorting to non-classical logics, or to non-normal or impossible worlds semantics. The framework combines, instead, a standard semantics for propositional S5 with a simple mereology of contents.

MSC:

03B42 Logics of knowledge and belief (including belief change)
03A05 Philosophical and critical aspects of logic and foundations

References:

[1] Alchourrón, C. E., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: Partial meet functions for contraction and revision. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510-530. · Zbl 0578.03011 · doi:10.2307/2274239
[2] Anderson, A. R., & Belnap, N. (1975). Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity I. Princeton: Princeton University Press. · Zbl 0323.02030
[3] Anderson, A. R., Belnap, N., & Dunn, J. M. (1992). Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity II. Princeton: Princeton University Press. · Zbl 0921.03025
[4] Angell, R. B. (1977). Three systems of first degree entailment. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 47, 147.
[5] Asheim, G., & Sövik, Y. (2005). Preference-based belief operators. Mathematical Social Sciences, 50, 61-82. · Zbl 1099.91033 · doi:10.1016/j.mathsocsci.2005.01.001
[6] Baltag, A.; Smets, S.; Bonanno, G. (ed.); Hoek, W. (ed.); Wooldridge, M. (ed.), A qualitative theory of dynamic interactive belief revision, 9-58 (2008), Amsterdam · Zbl 1261.03077
[7] Berto, F. (2013). Impossible worlds. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/impossible-worlds/.
[8] Berto, F. (2014). On conceiving the inconsistent. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 114, 21-103. · doi:10.1111/j.1467-9264.2014.00366.x
[9] Berto, F. (2017a). Aboutness in imagination. Philosophical Studies. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0937-y. · doi:10.1007/s11098-017-0937-y
[10] Berto, F. (2017b). Impossible worlds and the logic of imagination. Erkenntnis, 82, 1277-1297. · Zbl 1417.03044 · doi:10.1007/s10670-017-9875-5
[11] Board, O. (2004). Dynamic interactive epistemology. Games and Economic Behaviour, 49, 49-80. · Zbl 1068.91071 · doi:10.1016/j.geb.2003.10.006
[12] Bonanno, G. (2005). A simple modal logic for belief revision. Synthèse, 147, 193-228. · Zbl 1085.03012 · doi:10.1007/s11229-005-1348-8
[13] Chopra, S., & Parikh, R. (2000). Relevance sensitive belief structures. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 28, 259-285. · Zbl 1001.68095 · doi:10.1023/A:1018960323808
[14] Del Cerro, L. F., & Herzig, A. (1996). Belief change and dependence. In TARK proceedings, pp. 147-161.
[15] Fagin, R., & Halpern, J. (1988). Belief, awareness and limited reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, 34, 39-76. · Zbl 0634.03013 · doi:10.1016/0004-3702(87)90003-8
[16] Fagin, R., Halpern, J., Moses, Y., & Vardi, M. (1995). Reasoning about knowledge. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. · Zbl 0839.68095
[17] Ferguson, T. M. (2014). A computational interpretation of conceptivism. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logic, 24, 333-367. · Zbl 1398.03142 · doi:10.1080/11663081.2014.980116
[18] Fine, K. (1986). Analytic implication. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 27, 169-179. · Zbl 0621.03006 · doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1093636609
[19] Fine, K. (2015). Angellic content. Journal of Philosophical Logic. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-015-9371-9. · Zbl 1392.03030 · doi:10.1007/s10992-015-9371-9
[20] Floridi, L. (2005). Is information meaningful data? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(2), 351-370. · doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2005.tb00531.x
[21] French, R. (2017). A simple sequent calculus for angell’s logic of analytic containment. Studia Logica, 105(5), 971-994. · Zbl 1417.03164 · doi:10.1007/s11225-017-9719-y
[22] Gabbay, D. (1985). Theoretical foundations for non-monotonic reasoning. Berlin: Springer.
[23] Girard, P.; Rott, H.; Baltag, A. (ed.); Smets, S. (ed.), Belief revision and dynamic logic, 203-233 (2014), Dordrecht · Zbl 1408.03008
[24] Grove, A. (1988). Two modellings for theory change. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 17, 157-170. · Zbl 0639.03025 · doi:10.1007/BF00247909
[25] Hansson, S. O. (1999). A textbook of belief dynamics: Theory change and database updating. Dordrecht: Kluwer. · Zbl 0947.03023 · doi:10.1007/978-94-007-0814-3
[26] Hansson, S., & Wassermann, R. (2002). Local change. Studia Logica, 70, 49-76. · Zbl 1004.68163 · doi:10.1023/A:1014654208944
[27] Hawke, P. (2017). Theories of aboutness. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2017.1388826. · doi:10.1080/00048402.2017.1388826
[28] Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief. An introduction to the logic of the two notions. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
[29] Jago, M. (2007). Hintikka and cresswell on logical omniscience. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 15, 325-354. · Zbl 1134.03006 · doi:10.12775/LLP.2006.019
[30] Jago, M. (2014). The impossible. An essay on hyperintensionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. · doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198709008.001.0001
[31] Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1984). Choices, values, and frames. American Psychologist, 39, 341-350. · doi:10.1037/0003-066X.39.4.341
[32] Kiourti, I. (2010). Real impossible worlds: The bounds of possibility. PhD thesis, University of St Andrews.
[33] Kraus, S., Lehmann, D., & Magidor, M. (1990). Nonmonotonic reasoning, preferential models and cumulative logics. Artificial Intelligence, 44, 167-207. · Zbl 0782.03012 · doi:10.1016/0004-3702(90)90101-5
[34] Leitgeb, H., & Segerberg, K. (2005). Dynamic doxastic logic: Why, how, and where to? Synthèse, 155, 167-190. · Zbl 1120.03011 · doi:10.1007/s11229-006-9143-8
[35] Levesque, H. (1984). A logic of implicit and explicit belief. In National conference on AI, AAAI-84 (pp. 198-202).
[36] Levi, I. (1991). The fixation of belief and its undoing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. · doi:10.1017/CBO9780511663819
[37] Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.
[38] Lindström, S., & Rabinowicz, W. (1999). DDL unlimited: Dynamic doxastic logic for introspective agents. Erkenntnis, 50, 353-385. · Zbl 0969.03024 · doi:10.1023/A:1005577906029
[39] Meyer, JJ; Goble, L. (ed.), Epistemic logic, 182-202 (2001), Oxford
[40] Moss, LS; Baltag, A.; Solecki, S.; Gilboa, I. (ed.), The logic of public announcements, common knowledge, and private suspicions, 43-56 (1998), Evanston, IL
[41] Nolan, D. (1997). Impossible worlds: A modest approach. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 38, 535-572. · Zbl 0916.03013 · doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1039540769
[42] Peppas, P., Williams, M. A., & Chopra, S. (2015). Relevance in belief revision. Artificial Intelligence, 229, 126-138. · Zbl 1344.68223 · doi:10.1016/j.artint.2015.08.007
[43] Priest, G. (1987). In contradiction (2nd ed., Vol. 2006). Oxford: Oxford University Press. · doi:10.1007/978-94-009-3687-4
[44] Priest, G. (2001). An introduction to non-classical logic (2nd ed., Vol. 2008). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. · Zbl 0981.03002
[45] Rantala, V. (1982). Impossible world semantics and logical omniscience. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 35, 106-115. · Zbl 0519.03002
[46] Schipper, B.; Ditmarsch, H. (ed.); Halpern, J. (ed.); Hoek, W. (ed.); Kooi, B. (ed.), Awareness, 79-146 (2015), London
[47] Segerberg, K. (1995). Belief revision from the point of view of doxastic logic. Bulletin of the IGPL, 3, 535-553. · Zbl 0844.03015 · doi:10.1093/jigpal/3.4.535
[48] Spohn, W.; Hrper, LW (ed.); Skyrms, B. (ed.), Ordinal conditional functions: A dynamic theory of epistemic states, No. 2, 105-134 (1988), Dordrecht · doi:10.1007/978-94-009-2865-7_6
[49] Tanaka, K., Berto, F., Mares, E., & Paoli, F. (Eds.). (2013). Paraconsistency: Logic and applications. Dordrecht: Springer.
[50] van Benthem, J. (2007). Dynamic logic for belief revision. Journal of Applied Non-classical Logic, 17, 129-155. · Zbl 1186.03033 · doi:10.3166/jancl.17.129-155
[51] van Benthem, J. (2011). Logical dynamics of information and interaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. · Zbl 1251.03003 · doi:10.1017/CBO9780511974533
[52] Benthem, J.; Smets, S.; Ditmarsch, H. (ed.); Halpern, J. (ed.); Hoek, W. (ed.); Kooi, B. (ed.), Dynamic logics of belief change, 313-93 (2015), London
[53] van Ditmarsch, H. P. (2005). Prolegomena to dynamic logic for belief revision. Synthèse, 147, 229-275. · Zbl 1082.03014 · doi:10.1007/s11229-005-1349-7
[54] van Ditmarsch, H. P., van der Hoek, W., & Kooi, B. (2007). Dynamic epistemic logic. Dordrecht: Springer. · Zbl 1156.03015 · doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-5839-4
[55] Wansing, H. (1990). A general possible worlds framework for reasoning about knowledge and belief. Studia Logica, 49, 523-539. · Zbl 0744.03028 · doi:10.1007/BF00370163
[56] Yablo, S. (2014). Aboutness. Princeton: Princeton University Press. · doi:10.2307/j.ctt2tt8rv
This reference list is based on information provided by the publisher or from digital mathematics libraries. Its items are heuristically matched to zbMATH identifiers and may contain data conversion errors. In some cases that data have been complemented/enhanced by data from zbMATH Open. This attempts to reflect the references listed in the original paper as accurately as possible without claiming completeness or a perfect matching.