×

Negation on the Australian plan. (English) Zbl 1457.03007

Summary: We present and defend the Australian Plan semantics for negation. This is a comprehensive account, suitable for a variety of different logics. It is based on two ideas. The first is that negation is an exclusion-expressing device: we utter negations to express incompatibilities. The second is that, because incompatibility is modal, negation is a modal operator as well. It can, then, be modelled as a quantifier over points in frames, restricted by accessibility relations representing compatibilities and incompatibilities between such points. We defuse a number of objections to this Plan, raised by supporters of the American Plan for negation, in which negation is handled via a many-valued semantics. We show that the Australian Plan has substantial advantages over the American Plan.

MSC:

03A05 Philosophical and critical aspects of logic and foundations
03B45 Modal logic (including the logic of norms)
03B50 Many-valued logic
03B47 Substructural logics (including relevance, entailment, linear logic, Lambek calculus, BCK and BCI logics)

References:

[1] Barwise, J., & Etchemendy, J. (1990). Information, infons, and inference. In Cooper, R., Mukai, K., Perry, J. (Eds.) Situation theory and its applications, (Vol. 1, number 22 pp. 33-78). Stanford.
[2] Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Bradford books. MIT Press. · Zbl 0946.03007
[3] Beall, J.C. (2009). Spandrels of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press. · Zbl 1067.03500 · doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199268733.001.0001
[4] Beall, JC; Restall, G., Logical pluralism, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 475-493 (2000) · Zbl 1374.03001 · doi:10.1080/00048400012349751
[5] Beall, JC, & Restall, G. (2006). Logical pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. · Zbl 1374.03001
[6] Berto, F., Adynaton and material exclusion, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86, 165-90 (2008) · doi:10.1080/00048400801886199
[7] Berto, F., Absolute contradiction, dialetheism, and revenge, Review of Symbolic Logic, 7, 193-207 (2014) · Zbl 1329.03011 · doi:10.1017/S175502031400001X
[8] Berto, F., A modality called “negation”, Mind, 124, 761-793 (2015) · doi:10.1093/mind/fzv026
[9] Birkhoff, G.; von Neumann, J., The logic of quantum mechanics, The Annals of Mathematics, 37, 823-843 (1936) · JFM 62.1061.04 · doi:10.2307/1968621
[10] Brandom, R.B. (1994). Making it explicit. Harvard University Press.
[11] Brandom, R.B. (2000). Articulating reasons: an introduction to inferentialism. Harvard University Press. ISBN 0674001583.
[12] De, Michael; Omori, Hitoshi, There is More to Negation than Modality, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 47, 281-299 (2017) · Zbl 1436.03032 · doi:10.1007/s10992-017-9427-0
[13] Dunn, JM; Zhou, C., Negation in the context of gaggle theory, Studia Logica, 80, 235-64 (2005) · Zbl 1097.03015 · doi:10.1007/s11225-005-8470-y
[14] Dunn, J.M. (1993). Partial-gaggles applied to logics with restricted structural rules. In Schroeder-Heister, P., & Došen, K. (Eds.) Substructural logics: Oxford University Press. · Zbl 0941.03521
[15] Dunn, J.M. (1994). Star and perp: two treatments of negation. In Tomberlin, J.E. (Ed.) Philosophical perspectives. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2214128, (Vol. 7 pp. 331-357). Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing Company. · doi:10.2307/2214128
[16] Dunn, J.M. (1996). Generalised ortho negation. In Wansing, H. (Ed.) Negation: a notion in focus (pp. 3-26). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. · Zbl 0979.03027
[17] Novaes, C.D. (2007). Contradiction: the real philosophical challenge for paraconsistent logic. In Béziau, J.Y., Carnielli, W., Gabbay, D. (Eds.) Handbook of paraconsistency (pp. 477-92). London: College Publications. · Zbl 1230.03017
[18] Fine, K. (2009). The question of ontology. In Chalmers, D., Manley, D., Wasserman, R. (Eds.) Metametaphysics (pp. 157-77). Clarendon.
[19] Fitting, Melvin, Bilattices and the semantics of logic programming, The Journal of Logic Programming, 11, 91-116 (1991) · Zbl 0757.68028 · doi:10.1016/0743-1066(91)90014-G
[20] Goldblatt, R., Semantic analysis of orthologic, The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 3, 19-35 (1974) · Zbl 0278.02023 · doi:10.1007/BF00652069
[21] Grim, P. (2004). What is a contradiction? In Priest, G., Beall, J.C., Armour-Garb, B. (Eds.) The law of non-contradiction (pp. 49-72). Clarendon. · Zbl 1061.03009
[22] Incurvati, L.; Schlöder, JJ, Weak rejection, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 95, 741-760 (2017) · doi:10.1080/00048402.2016.1277771
[23] Kripke, S. (1965). Semantical analysis of intuitionistic logic. In Crossley, J., & Dummett, M.A.E. (Eds.) Formal Systems and Recursive Functions (pp. 92-130). Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing. · Zbl 0137.00702
[24] Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.
[25] Lewis, D.K. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.
[26] Mares, ED, A star-free semantics for R, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 60, 579-590 (1995) · Zbl 0833.03008 · doi:10.2307/2275852
[27] Mares, E.D. (2004). Relevant logic. A philosophical interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University press. · doi:10.1017/CBO9780511520006
[28] Meyer, RK; Martin, EP, Logic on the australian plan, The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 15, 305-332 (1986) · Zbl 0614.03006 · doi:10.1007/BF00248574
[29] Price, H., Why ‘not’?, Mind, 99, 221-38 (1990) · doi:10.1093/mind/XCIX.394.221
[30] Priest, G. (2008). An introduction to non-classical logic, 2nd edn. Vol. 2008. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. · Zbl 1148.03002
[31] Restall, G., Four-valued semantics for relevant logics (and some of their rivals), Journal of Philosophical Logic, 24, 139-69 (1993) · Zbl 0815.03014 · doi:10.1007/BF01048529
[32] Restall, G. (1995). Information flow and relevant logics. In Seligman, J., & Westerståhl, D. (Eds.) Logic, language and computation: the 1994 Moraga proceedings (pp. 463-477). · Zbl 0877.03015
[33] Restall, G. (1999). Negation in relevant logics (how i stopped worrying and learned to love the Routley star). In Gabbay, D., & Wansing, H. (Eds.) What is negation? (pp. 53-76). Dordrecht: Kluwer. · Zbl 0974.03026
[34] Restall, G. (2000). An introduction to substructural logics. Routledge. · Zbl 1028.03018
[35] Restall, G., Defining double negation elimination, The Logic Journal of the IGPL, 8, 853-860 (2000) · Zbl 0980.03033 · doi:10.1093/jigpal/8.6.853
[36] Restall, G. (2005). Multiple conclusions. In Hájek, P., Valdés-Villanueva, L., Westerståhl, D. (Eds.) Logic, methodology and philosophy of science: proceedings of the twelfth international congress (pp. 189-205): KCL Publications. http://consequently.org/writing/multipleconclusions. · Zbl 1105.03011
[37] Restall, G., Truth values and proof theory, Studia Logica, 92, 241-264 (2009) · Zbl 1191.03042 · doi:10.1007/s11225-009-9197-y
[38] Ripley, D., Paradoxes and failures of cut, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91, 139-164 (2013) · doi:10.1080/00048402.2011.630010
[39] Routley, R.; Meyer, RK, The semantics of entailment II, Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1, 53-73 (1972) · Zbl 0317.02018 · doi:10.1007/BF00649991
[40] Routley, R., & Meyer, R.K. (1973). The semantics of entailment I. In Leblanc, H. (Ed.) Truth, syntax, and semantics (pp. 194-243). North-Holland. · Zbl 0317.02017
[41] Routley, R., The American plan completed: alternative classical-style semantics, without stars, for relevant and paraconsistent logics, Studia Logica, 43, 131-158 (1984) · Zbl 0583.03012 · doi:10.1007/BF00935746
[42] Routley, R.; Routley, V., Semantics of first degree entailment, Noûs, 6, 335-359 (1972) · Zbl 1366.03122 · doi:10.2307/2214309
[43] Stalnaker, Robert C., A Theory of Conditionals, 41-55 (1968), Dordrecht · doi:10.1007/978-94-009-9117-0_2
[44] Tahko, T., The law of non-contradiction as a metaphysical principle, Australasian Journal of Logic, 7, 32-47 (2009) · Zbl 1330.03027 · doi:10.26686/ajl.v7i0.1806
[45] Tennant, N. (1999). Negation, absurdity and contrariety. In Gabbay, D., & Wansing, H. (Eds.) What Is negation? (pp. 199-222). Dordrecht: Kluwer. · Zbl 0981.03007
[46] Tye, M., Vague objects, Mind, XCIX, 535 (1990) · doi:10.1093/mind/XCIX.396.535
[47] Wansing, Heinrich, Negation, 415-436 (2017), Oxford, UK · Zbl 1010.03006 · doi:10.1002/9781405164801.ch18
[48] Wansing, H., Constructive negation, implication, and co-implication, Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics, 18, 341-364 (2008) · Zbl 1181.03027 · doi:10.3166/jancl.18.341-364
[49] Wiggins, D. (2001). Sameness and substance renewed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. · doi:10.1017/CBO9780511612756
This reference list is based on information provided by the publisher or from digital mathematics libraries. Its items are heuristically matched to zbMATH identifiers and may contain data conversion errors. In some cases that data have been complemented/enhanced by data from zbMATH Open. This attempts to reflect the references listed in the original paper as accurately as possible without claiming completeness or a perfect matching.