Ernest van den Haag (September 15, 1914 – March 21, 2002) was a Dutch-born American sociologist, social critic, and author. He was John M. Olin Professor of Jurisprudence and Public Policy at Fordham University. He was best known for his contributions to National Review.
Ernest van den Haag | |
---|---|
Born | September 15, 1914 The Hague, Netherlands |
Died | March 21, 2002 |
Alma mater | University of Iowa |
Life and career
editErnest van den Haag was born in 1914 in the Hague to Moses "Max" Melamerson and Flora Haag Melamerson. He changed his surname in the early 1940s. While van den Haag was still young, his family moved to Italy. Van den Haag grew up in Italy, and following his education began a life in politics. In the late 1930s, he was a left-wing activist and communist. During this time, Italy was ruled by Benito Mussolini's fascist regime. In 1937, van den Haag was nearly murdered by a political assassin who shot him five times. After being shot, he spent nearly three years in prison. Nearly eighteen months of those three years were spent in solitary confinement. After release, fearing re-imprisonment, van den Haag drifted between European countries in an attempt to evade Italy and Mussolini. In 1940, he made his way to Portugal and fled to the United States, arriving at Ellis Island, not knowing any English. Living in New York, van den Haag worked as a bus boy and sold vegetables; eventually he was able to secure admission to the University at Iowa, where a group of faculty members recognized his intellectual gifts and agreed to pay for his tuition. In 1942, van den Haag graduated with an M.A in economics. The same year, van den Haag met the political philosopher Sidney Hook. His friendship with Hook forever changed van den Haag, converting him from being a left-wing activist and communist, to the opposite end of the spectrum; van den Haag was now a conservative. Over the years, van den Haag took particular interest in the field of capital punishment and the death penalty. His book Punishing Criminals: Concerning a Very Old and Painful Question (1975) developed his reputation on being one of the foremost thinkers and proponents on the death penalty. Van den Haag was considered by his colleagues to be an expert on the issue of capital punishment.[1]
Van den Haag died in Mendham, New Jersey.
On racial segregation in public schools
editHe was an early opponent of the Supreme Court's decision in Brown v. Board of Education which found segregation in schools unconstitutional,[2] and testified in favor of segregation.[3] He also argued that continued school segregation was desirable because of the "genetic intellectual inferiority" of black students. In a National Review cover-page article, van den Haag dismissed recent research undermining the notion of innate ethnic differences in intelligence, stating that he believed such differences existed and accounted for "much" of the poorer academic performance of black students, thus necessitating separate schooling.[4] This article caused controversy among readers of the National Review, several of whom wrote angry letters against the decision to print such "bigotry".[5] In 1966, he testified before the International Court of Justice in support of apartheid in South Africa.[6]
On race-neutrality in U.S. immigration policy
editIn another article, from 1965, he opposed the Immigration and Nationality Act of 1965, which replaced an immigration system largely excluding Asians and discriminating against southern and eastern Europeans with a race-neutral program based on skills and family connections to U.S. citizens and permanent residents, which enabled an increase in immigration from Asia. Van den Haag instead advocated greater rather than less immigration restriction. He also expressly defended the practice of fashioning immigration policies in favor of European ethnicity, arguing that "The wish to preserve... the identity of one's nation requires no justification." He likened such a practice to a harmless expression of sentiment, similar to preferring to associate with one's own family rather than strangers. "The wish not to see one's country overrun by groups one regards as alien need not be based on feelings of superiority or 'racism.'"[7]
On the death penalty
editVan den Haag's particular field of interest, the field he contributed the most to in terms of publications, was the death penalty, particularly in the context of the capital punishment debate in the United States before and after the Furman v. Georgia ruling in 1972, which (temporarily) abolished capital punishment nationwide. Van den Haag was a respected debater, and when he was not contributing to the National Review or other publications, he was active in debating the issue of the death penalty. His main argument in its defence stemmed from key themes such as deterrence, and retributive punishment for severe criminals.[8] On Firing Line, he joined a programme dedicated to the death penalty debate on December 13, 1976, after the Gregg v. Georgia ruling (but weeks before the resumption of executions with Gary Gilmore, who was a subject of the deterrence argument) and was cited in a previous programme with Truman Capote in 1968, regarding an off-cam argument with regard to the efficiency of the punishment, which Capote challenged.[9]
In his book Punishing Criminals, van den Haag defines the primary role of government as "securing rights and duties by specifying them through laws and enforcing the laws."[10] Van den Haag believed the paramount duty of government is to "provide legal order in which citizens can be secure in their lives, their liberties, and their pursuit of happiness."[11] The law exists to provide legal order. Van den Haag disputed claims that capital punishment is just a form of legal retribution by claiming that if laws are knowingly broken, legal order can only be maintained by enforcement. Justice, van den Haag claimed, is blindfolded, while retribution carries the weight of passion behind it; justice being delivered to someone who violates social order knowingly is equal, thus the term legal retribution is void.[12]
Van den Haag also argued that people commit crimes because they believe, one way or another, they will benefit from committing the crime. Thus it is society's duty to make all crimes as disadvantageous as possible. Van den Haag uses economic examples to further prove his point. In economics, there is a concept named opportunity cost. Opportunity cost forces an individual to weigh the benefits versus the sacrifices of making a decision. Van den Haag believes people look at committing the crime the same way they would view an opportunity; they would weigh the profits versus the punishment. Temptation to commit a crime will be significantly decreased if the punishment for committing the crime is more severe.[13] The death penalty offers the greatest weighted punishment for committing an offense. Van den Haag also related Marxist theory behind his justification of the death penalty. Marxists, Van den Haag argued, believe that "Legal justice never can do less, though it can do more."[14] Legal justice should distribute punishment equally among violators and more frequently in order to deter crime.[15] Van den Haag also related to the Marxist belief in class warfare. Van den Haag states, "Obviously, the poor and powerless are more tempted to take what is not theirs, or to rebel, than the powerful and wealthy, who need not take what they already have."[16] The threat of severe punishment diminishes temptation, which van den Haag argued is to be the greatest use of the death penalty, deterrence.
Van den Haag also believed that law breakers have more of an inclination to repeat their bad actions. He said that breaking the law leads to a form of moral decay, in which offenders can no longer distinguish right from wrong, and thus repeat offending is common. To lower the crime rate, and the tendency of individuals toward committing more violent crimes over time, van den Haag said, "The only permanent, and irrevocable incapacitation is execution."[17] Van den Haag believed that any temporary or permanent incapacitation only reduces the crime rate if there are no more compensating increases in crime by other people. He argued that, without the strong deterrent effect of a death penalty, an increase in crime and criminals remains a factor.[18] Van den Haag believed homicide to be the most deplorable crime a human being can commit. In his book The Death Penalty : A Debate, he argues that "the state must teach that killing anyone deliberately, for whatever reason, is needless and wrong."[19]
Van den Haag believed that capital punishment has a direct correlation with a decrease in murders. Rehabilitation as a response to criminals who murder is not an option because, as van den Haag states, "no effective method to achieve it [rehabilitation] has been found."[20] He said that, even if a proper method of rehabilitation can be found, it would not reduce the crime rate, because rehabilitation only works after the crime has been committed, i.e. in the case of murder, once an innocent life had been lost. He argued that deterrence is the only thing that can have any effect on the actual crime rate. Overall, van den Haag directed his argument toward the fact that the death penalty ought only to exist to protect innocent lives. To sum up his entire argument against his opposition in one quote, van den Haag contends, "I'd rather execute a man convicted of having murdered others than put the lives of innocents at risk. I find it hard to understand the opposite choice."[21]
While he recognized that innocent people would sometimes be executed, Van den Haag contended that no penalty was irreversible, except for fines, and that while an execution (once performed) was also irrevocable - that is, could not be undone or set aside - the notion of sentencing innocents to prison time unduly was equally disturbing, and in no way certain to be discovered. As the prospect of execution would purportedly harden a jury not to impose a guilty verdict easily, the irrevocability sentiment viz. a life sentence would make a court more prone to mistakes, also with disastrous consequences. The innocence argument, in Van den Haag's mind, thus must be aimed at the justice system, and not exclusively against a punishment as such.[22][23]
Published works (selection)
editThroughout his life, Ernest van den Haag wrote many books and articles about society, and more specifically about capital punishment. His works include:
- The Death Penalty: A Debate, 1983 (co-authored with John P. Conrad)
- The Jewish Mystique, 1968
- Political violence and civil disobedience, 1972
- Punishing Criminals: Concerning a Very Old and Painful Question, 1975
References
edit- ^ "Ernest van den Haag Papers, 1935-2000 - M.E. Grenander Department of Special Collections & Archives".
- ^ Ernest van den Haag, Social Science Testimony in the Desegregation Cases – A Reply to Professor Kenneth Clark, 6 Villanova Law Review 69(1960)
- ^ Raymond Wolters, Race and Education, 1954–2007, 37–38 (2008)
- ^ Ernest van den Haag, "Intelligence or Prejudice?," in National Review XVI, No. 48 (December 1, 1964) pp. 1059–63.
- ^ "Intelligence or Prejudice?: Some Letters and a Reply," in National Review (February 9, 1965) pp. 101–02
- ^ John P. Jackson, Jr., Science For Segregation: Race, Law, and the Case Against Brown v. Board of Education 143 (2005)
- ^ Ernest van den Haag, "More Immigration?," in National Review (September 21, 1965) pp. 821–22, 842.
- ^ M. E. Grenander Department of Special Collections & Archives, "Archives of Public Affairs "Finding Aid for the Ernest van den Haag Papers, 1935–2000"." Accessed November 19, 2012.
- ^ "Firing Line with William F. Buckley Jr.: The Death Penalty". YouTube. 30 January 2017.
- ^ Van den Haag, Ernest, Punishing Criminals: Concerning a Very Old and Painful Question, (New York: Basic Books, 1975), p. 1.
- ^ Van den Haag, p. 1.
- ^ Van den Haag, p. 11.
- ^ Van den Haag, p. 20.
- ^ Van den Haag, p. 32.
- ^ Van den Haag, p. 33.
- ^ Van den Haag, p. 45.
- ^ Van den Haag, p. 51.
- ^ Van den Haag, p. 52
- ^ Van den Haag, Ernest, The Death Penalty: a Debate. (New York: Plenum Press, 1983), p. 10.
- ^ Van den Haag, Ernest, The Death Penalty: a Debate, p. 53.
- ^ Ernest van den Haag, The Death Penalty: a Debatep. 69.
- ^ Elizabeth Linehan, Executing the Innocent ("As Ernest Van Den Haag says, 'The conviction of some innocents is an unintended, yet unavoidable, byproduct of bringing the guilty to justice.'")
- ^ https://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?referer=&httpsredir=1&article=5580&context=jclc [bare URL]