×

Mathematizing as a virtuous practice: different narratives and their consequences for mathematics education and society. (English) Zbl 1529.00025

Summary: There are different narratives on mathematics as part of our world, some of which are more appropriate than others. Such narratives might be of the form ‘Mathematics is useful’, ‘Mathematics is beautiful’, or ‘Mathematicians aim at theorem-credit’. These narratives play a crucial role in mathematics education and in society as they are influencing people’s willingness to engage with the subject or the way they interpret mathematical results in relation to real-world questions; the latter yielding important normative considerations. Our strategy is to frame current narratives of mathematics from a virtue-theoretic perspective. We identify the practice of mathematizing, put forward by Freudenthal’s ‘Realistic mathematics education’, as virtuous and use it to evaluate different narratives. We show that this can help to render the narratives more adequately, and to provide implications for societal organization.

MSC:

00A35 Methodology of mathematics
00A30 Philosophy of mathematics
97D20 Philosophical and theoretical contributions (didactics of mathematics)

References:

[1] Aigner, M.; Ziegler, G., Proofs from THE BOOK (2004), Berlin: Springer, Berlin · Zbl 1098.00001
[2] Azzouni, J., The derivation-indicator view of mathematical practice, Philosophia Mathematica, 12, 2, 81-106 (2004) · Zbl 1136.00301
[3] Azzouni, J., Why do informal proofs conform to formal norms?, Foundations of Science, 14, 1-2, 9-26 (2009) · Zbl 1182.03009
[4] Barbeau, E.; Howson, A.; Kahane, J., Mathematics for the public, The popularization of mathematics (ICMI studies), 41-50 (1990), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Cambridge · Zbl 0871.00015
[5] Barwise, J.; Barwise, J., An introduction to first-order logic, Handbook of mathematical logic, 5-46 (1977), Amsterdam: North-Holland, Amsterdam
[6] Berk, L. A. (1982). Hilbert’s thesis: Some considerations about formalizations of mathematics. Ph.D. Thesis, MIT, Online available via http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/15650. Accessed May 4, 2020.
[7] Bishop, JP, “She’s always been the smart one. I’ve always been the dumb one”: Identities in the mathematics classroom, Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 43, 1, 34-74 (2012)
[8] Bogen, J.; Woodward, J., Saving the phenomena, The Philosophical Review, 97, 3, 303-352 (1988)
[9] Carl, M., & Koepke, P. (2014). Interpreting naproche—An algorithmic approach to the derivation-indicator view. In 36th annual convention of the society for the study of artificial intelligence and the simulation of behaviour (AISB 2010): Proceedings (pp. 7-10). London: AISB.
[10] Cartwright, N., How the laws of physics lie (1983), Oxford: Oxford University Press, Oxford
[11] Colli, E., Nemenzo, F., Polthier, K., & Rousseau, C. (2014). Mathematics is everywhere. In S. Y. Jang, Y. R. Kim, D.-W. Lee & I. Yie (Eds.) Proceedings of the international congress of mathematicians, Seoul 2014 (Vol. 1, pp. 799-811), Seoul: Kyung Moon SA. · Zbl 1375.00002
[12] Corfield, D.; Doxiadis, A.; Mazur, B., Narrative and the rationality of mathematical practice, Circles disturbed: The interplay of mathematics and narrative, 244-280 (2012), Princeton: Princeton University Press, Princeton · Zbl 1237.00022
[13] Davis, PJ; Hersh, R., The mathematical experience (1998), Boston: Houghton Mifflin, Boston
[14] Díaz, C.; de la Fuente, I., Assessing students’ difficulties with conditional probability and Bayesian reasoning, International Electronic Journal of Mathematics Education, 2, 3, 128-148 (2007)
[15] Dieudonné, J., New thinking in school mathematics (1961), Paris: Organization for European Economic Cooperation, Paris
[16] Dreyfus, T.; Eisenberg, T., On the aesthetics of mathematical thought, For the Learning of Mathematics, 6, 2-10 (1986)
[17] Ernest, P., Values, gender and images of mathematics: A philosophical perspective, International Journal of Mathematical Education in Science and Technology, 26, 3, 449-462 (1995) · Zbl 0864.00011
[18] Ernest, P., Values and the social responsibility of mathematics, Critical Issues in Mathematics Education, 6, 207-216 (2009)
[19] Ernest, P., The collateral damage of learning mathematics, Philosophy of Mathematics Education Journal, 31, 1-24 (2016)
[20] Freudenthal, H., Why to teach mathematics so as to be useful?, Educational Studies in Mathematics, 1, 3-8 (1968)
[21] Freudenthal, H., Mathematics as an educational task (1973), Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing, Dordrecht · Zbl 0246.00013
[22] Freudenthal, H., Didactical phenomenology of mathematical structures (1983), Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing, Dordrecht
[23] Freudenthal, H., Revisiting mathematics Education: China lectures (1991), Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht
[24] Gallagher, J. (2014). Mathematics: Why the brain sees maths as beauty. BBC News, Online available via https://www.bbc.com/news/science-environment-26151062. Accessed May 4, 2020.
[25] Gonthier, G., Formal proof—The four-color theorem, Notices of the American Mathematical Society, 55, 11, 1382-1393 (2008) · Zbl 1195.05026
[26] Gonthier, G., Asperti, A., Avigad, J., Bertot, Y., Cohen, C., Garillot, F., & Pasca, I. (2013). A machine-checked proof of the odd order theorem. In International conference on interactive theorem proving (pp. 163-179). Berlin: Springer. · Zbl 1317.68211
[27] Gowers, WT; Arnold, V.; Atiyah, M.; Lax, P.; Mazur, B., The two cultures of mathematics, Mathematics: Frontiers and perspectives, 65-78 (2000), Province: American Mathematical Society, Province · Zbl 0998.00003
[28] Gowers, WT; Doxiadis, A.; Mazur, B., Vividness in mathematics and narrative, Circles disturbed: The interplay of mathematics and narrative, 211-231 (2012), Princeton: Princeton University Press, Princeton · Zbl 1237.00022
[29] Gravemeijer, K.; Doorman, M., Context problems in realistic mathematics education: A calculus course as an example, Educational Studies in Mathematics, 39, 1-3, 111-129 (1999)
[30] Hipolito, I.; Kahle, R., Discussing Hilbert’s 24th problem, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A, 377, 1-10 (2019) · Zbl 1441.03006
[31] Inglis, M.; Aberdein, A., Beauty is not simplicity: An analysis of mathematicians’ proof appraisals, Philosophia Mathematica, 23, 1, 87-109 (2015) · Zbl 1357.00018
[32] Inglis, M.; Aberdein, A.; Larvor, B., Diversity in proof appraisal, Mathematical cultures, 163-179 (2016), Cham: Birkhäuser, Cham · Zbl 07907741
[33] Jech, T., Set theory (2006), Berlin: Springer, Berlin
[34] Kahle, R., Is there a “Hilbert thesis”?, Studia Logica, 107, 1, 145-165 (2019) · Zbl 1428.03021
[35] Kahle, R.; Oitavem, I., What is Hilbert’s 24th problem?, Kairos, 20, 1, 1-11 (2018)
[36] Kaiser, G., Modelling in mathematics education—Theoretical perspectives, examples and experiences, Chinese Mathematical Bulletin, 65, 27-38 (2010)
[37] Kaiser, G.; Schwarz, B., Authentic modelling problems in mathematics education—Examples and experiences, Journal für Mathematik-Didaktik, 31, 1-2, 51-76 (2010)
[38] Kießwetter, K. (2006). Können Grundschüler schon im eigentlichen Sinne mathematisch agieren. und was kann man von mathematisch besonders begabten Grundschülern erwarten, und was noch nicht? In H. Bauersfeld & K. Kießwetter (Eds.) Wie fördert man mathematisch besonders befähigte Kinder? Ein Buch aus der Praxis für die Praxis (pp. 128-153). Offenburg: Mildenberger.
[39] King, NL, Erratum to: Perseverance as an intellectual virtue, Synthese, 191, 15, 3779-3801 (2014)
[40] Kultusministerkonferenz. (2009). Empfehlung der Kultusministerkonferenz zur Stärkung der mathematisch-naturwissenschaftlich-technischen Bildung (Beschluss der Kultusministerkonferenz vom 07.05.2009).
[41] Lakatos, I., Proofs and refutations (edited by John Worrall and Elie Zahar) (1976), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Cambridge · Zbl 0334.00022
[42] Lakoff, G.; Núñez, R., Where mathematics comes from (2000), New York: Basic Books, New York · Zbl 0987.00003
[43] Leitgeb, H.; Bueno, O.; Linnebo, Ø., On formal and informal provability, New waves in philosophy of mathematics, 263-299 (2009), London: Palgrave Macmillan, London · Zbl 1261.03035
[44] Maddy, P., Defending the axioms: On the philosophical foundations of set theory (2011), Oxford: Oxford University Press, Oxford · Zbl 1219.00014
[45] Margolin, U.; Doxiadis, A.; Mazur, B., Mathematics and narrative: A narratological perspective, Circles disturbed: The interplay of mathematics and narrative, 481-507 (2012), Princeton: Princeton University Press, Princeton · Zbl 1237.00022
[46] Mason, J.; Watson, A.; Carlson, M.; Rasmussen, C., Mathematics as constructive activity: Exploiting dimensions of possible variation, Making the connection: Research and practice in undergraduate mathematics, 191-204 (2008), Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of America, Washington, DC · Zbl 1139.97001
[47] McMullin, E., Galilean idealization, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 16, 3, 247-273 (1985)
[48] Moreau, MP; Mendick, H.; Epstein, D.; Watson, E., Constructions of ‘mathematical man’ in popular culture, Pimps, wimps, studs, thugs and gentlemen: Essays on media images of masculinity, 141-156 (2009), Jefferson: McFarland Publishers, Jefferson
[49] Moreau, MP; Mendick, H.; Epstein, D., Constructions of mathematicians in popular culture and learners’ narratives: A study of mathematical and non-mathematical subjectivities, Cambridge Journal of Education, 40, 1, 25-38 (2010)
[50] Nasar, S., & Gruber, D. (2006). Manifold destiny: A legendary problem and the battle over who solved it. The New Yorker, Online aviable via https://www.newyorker.com/magazine/2006/08/28/manifold-destiny. Accessed May 4, 2020. · Zbl 1239.00040
[51] Neale, V. (2017). Mathematics is beautiful (no, really). The Conversation, Online available via https://theconversation.com/mathematics-is-beautiful-no-really-72921. Accessed May 4, 2020.
[52] Nolte, M.; Pamperien, K., Challenging problems in a regular classroom setting and in a special foster programme, ZDM Mathematics Education, 49, 1, 121-136 (2017)
[53] Olsson, K. (2019). The aesthetic beauty of math. The Paris Review, Online available via https://www.theparisreview.org/blog/2019/07/22/the-aesthetic-beauty-of-math/. Accessed May 4, 2020.
[54] Peterson, I., Searching for new mathematics, SIAM Review, 33, 1, 37-42 (1991)
[55] Peterson (1996). Searching for new mathematics. (Articles on Public Understanding of Math). http://forum.swarthmore.edu/social/articles/ivars.html.
[56] Picker, SH; Berry, JS, Investigating pupils’ images of mathematicians, Educational Studies in Mathematics, 43, 1, 65-94 (2000)
[57] Roberts, S. (2017). The beauty of mathematics: It can never lie to you. Wired, Online available via https://www.wired.com/2017/03/beauty-mathematics-can-never-lie/. Accessed May 4, 2020.
[58] Sam, L. C. (1999). Public images of mathematics. PhD Thesis. University of Exeter, United Kingdom.
[59] Schukajlow, S.; Kaiser, G.; Stillman, G., Empirical research on teaching and learning of mathematical modelling: A survey on the current-state-of-the-art, ZDM Mathematics Education, 50, 1-2, 5-18 (2018)
[60] Shelah, S. (2002). You can enter Cantor’s paradise! Conference paper at Paul Erdös and his mathematics; 1999; Budapest. Bolyai Society Mathematical Studies (Vol. 11, pp. 555-564). Springer, Janos Bolyai Mathematical Society. · Zbl 1030.03042
[61] Sinclair, N., The aesthetic “Is” relevant, For the Learning of Mathematics, 21, 1, 25-32 (2001)
[62] Sinclair, N., Aesthetic values in mathematics: A value-oriented epistemology, International Group for the Psychology of Mathematics Education, 4, 199-205 (2003)
[63] Tall, D., Looking at graphs through infinitesimal microscopes, windows and telescopes, Mathematical Gazette, 64, 22-49 (1980) · Zbl 0499.26008
[64] Tall, D., The anatomy of discovery in mathematical research, For the Learning of Mathematics, 1, 2, 25-30 (1980)
[65] Tall, D., Advanced mathematical thinking (1991), Dodrecht: Kluwer, Dodrecht · Zbl 0848.00010
[66] Tall, D., How humans learn to think mathematically (2013), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
[67] Tanswell, F., A problem with the dependence of informal proofs on formal proofs, Philosophia Mathematica, 23, 3, 295-310 (2015) · Zbl 1357.00027
[68] Tanswell, F. (2017). Proof, rigour and informality: A virtue account of mathematical knowledge. Ph.D. Thesis, University of St Andrews.
[69] Teissier, B.; Doxiadis, A.; Mazur, B., Mathematics and narrative: Why are stories and proofs interesting?, Circles disturbed: The interplay of mathematics and narrative, 232-243 (2012), Princeton: Princeton University Press, Princeton · Zbl 1237.00022
[70] Treffers, A., Three dimensions. A model of goal and theory description in mathematics instruction—The Wiskobas Project (1987), Dodrecht: Reidel Publishing Company, Dodrecht
[71] Tymoczko, T.; White, AM, Value judgements in mathematics: Can we treat mathematics as an art?, Essays in humanistic mathematics, 66-77 (1993), Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of America, Washington, DC
[72] Van Den Heuvel-Panhuizen, M., The didactical use of models in realistic mathematics education: An example from a longitudinal trajectory on percentage, Educational Studies in Mathematics, 54, 9-35 (2003)
[73] Van den Heuvel-Panhuizen, M.; Drijvers, P.; Lerman, S., Realistic mathematics education, Encyclopedia of mathematics education, 521-525 (2014), Dordrecht: Springer, Dordrecht · Zbl 1279.97005
[74] Weisberg, M., Three kinds of idealization, The Journal of Philosophy, 104, 12, 639-659 (2007)
[75] Woodward, JF, Data and phenomena. A restatement and defense, Synthese, 182, 1, 165-179 (2011)
This reference list is based on information provided by the publisher or from digital mathematics libraries. Its items are heuristically matched to zbMATH identifiers and may contain data conversion errors. In some cases that data have been complemented/enhanced by data from zbMATH Open. This attempts to reflect the references listed in the original paper as accurately as possible without claiming completeness or a perfect matching.