×

Another use of set theory. (English) Zbl 0932.03068

Traditionally, there have been two uses of set theory. In the first decades of this century it became apparent that every mathematical object could be represented as a set, and therefore that set theory could be used as a foundational system. According to Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem no formal system can exhaustively describe the whole mathematical universe, and therefore the point is no longer actually to prove properties of sets, but rather to calibrate them in a scale of increasingly strong logical axioms. The author, analysing some recent applications of set theory to algebra and topology, shows that set theory has been used to crystallize some intuitions for which other frameworks would be too rigid, and to elaborate them with the help of its specific tools, including strong axioms. This role is distinct from the previous ones in that all strong axioms are subsequently eliminated from the picture, so that the final results have no link with set-theoretical hypotheses. When the use of the additional axiom proves to be necessary, this gives rise to the second use of set theory. But if, on the contrary, the set-theoretical axiom can be eliminated, then the additional principle gives only a sort of plausibility before one discovers the final proof. From this point of view, the stronger the axiom is, the more powerful it is likely to be in terms of applications. The author believes that this new role of set theory could help to revitalize the interest in set theory in the future.

MSC:

03E75 Applications of set theory
00A30 Philosophy of mathematics
00A35 Methodology of mathematics

References:

[1] Mathematical Intelligencer 16 pp 31– (1994)
[2] The higher infinite (1994)
[3] DOI: 10.1007/BF02760522 · Zbl 0596.03055 · doi:10.1007/BF02760522
[4] DOI: 10.1016/0001-8708(81)90021-9 · Zbl 0483.03030 · doi:10.1016/0001-8708(81)90021-9
[5] DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(71)90018-0 · Zbl 0215.32702 · doi:10.1016/0003-4843(71)90018-0
[6] Advances in Mathematics
[7] DOI: 10.1142/S0218216595000041 · Zbl 0873.20030 · doi:10.1142/S0218216595000041
[8] DOI: 10.1090/S0002-9947-1994-1214782-4 · doi:10.1090/S0002-9947-1994-1214782-4
[9] DOI: 10.1016/0168-0072(88)90028-0 · Zbl 0646.03030 · doi:10.1016/0168-0072(88)90028-0
[10] Advances in Mathematics
[11] Handbook of mathematical logic (1977)
[12] Séminaire Bourbaki pp 715– (1989)
[13] Mathematical Intelligencer 14 pp 63– (1992)
[14] Set theory of the continuum pp 119– (1992)
[15] DOI: 10.1090/S0894-0347-1989-0955605-X · doi:10.1090/S0894-0347-1989-0955605-X
[16] DOI: 10.1006/aima.1995.1014 · Zbl 0822.03031 · doi:10.1006/aima.1995.1014
[17] DOI: 10.1016/0001-8708(92)90016-E · Zbl 0822.03030 · doi:10.1016/0001-8708(92)90016-E
[18] DOI: 10.1007/BF01188182 · Zbl 0793.08007 · doi:10.1007/BF01188182
[19] Set theory of the continuum pp 119– (1992)
[20] DOI: 10.1112/blms/14.4.285 · Zbl 0501.03017 · doi:10.1112/blms/14.4.285
[21] Knots and physics (1991) · Zbl 0733.57004
[22] DOI: 10.1016/0003-4843(78)90031-1 · Zbl 0376.02055 · doi:10.1016/0003-4843(78)90031-1
This reference list is based on information provided by the publisher or from digital mathematics libraries. Its items are heuristically matched to zbMATH identifiers and may contain data conversion errors. In some cases that data have been complemented/enhanced by data from zbMATH Open. This attempts to reflect the references listed in the original paper as accurately as possible without claiming completeness or a perfect matching.